547 lines
34 KiB
Markdown
547 lines
34 KiB
Markdown
**C.1.1 Is economics really value free?** is the second chapter of
|
||
[Section
|
||
C](Section_C:_What_are_the_myths_of_capitalist_economics?_\(An_Anarchist_FAQ\) "wikilink")
|
||
of [An Anarchist FAQ](An_Anarchist_FAQ "wikilink").
|
||
|
||
## Transcript
|
||
|
||
Modern economists try and portray economics as a “value-free
|
||
[science](science "wikilink").” Of course, it rarely dawns on them that
|
||
they are usually just taking existing social structures for granted and
|
||
building economic dogmas around them, so justifying them. At best, as
|
||
[Kropotkin](Peter_Kropotkin "wikilink") pointed out: “\[A\]ll the
|
||
so-called laws and theories of political economy are in reality no more
|
||
than statements of the following nature: ‘Granting that there are always
|
||
in a country a considerable number of [people who cannot subsist a
|
||
month, or even a fortnight, without earning a
|
||
salary](Working_Class "wikilink") and accepting for that purpose the
|
||
conditions of work imposed upon them by the
|
||
[State](State_\(Polity\) "wikilink"), or offered to them by those whom
|
||
the [State recognises as owners ofland, factories, railways,
|
||
etc.](Capitalism "wikilink"), then the results will be so and so. ’“So
|
||
far academic political economy has been only an enumeration of what
|
||
happens under these conditions — without distinctly stating the
|
||
conditions themselves. And then,having described the facts which arise
|
||
in our society under these conditions, they represent to us these facts
|
||
as rigid, inevitable economic laws.”\[Anarchism, p. 179\]
|
||
|
||
In other words, economists usually take the political and economic
|
||
aspects of capitalist society (such as property rights, inequality and
|
||
so on) as given and construct their theories around it. At best. At
|
||
worse, economics is simply speculation based on the necessary
|
||
assumptions required to prove the desired end. By some strange
|
||
coincidence these ends usually bolster the power and profits of the few
|
||
and show that the free market is the best of all possible worlds. Alfred
|
||
Marshall, one of the founders of neoclassical economics, once noted the
|
||
usefulness of economics to the elite: “From Metaphysics I went to
|
||
Ethics, and found that the justification of the existing conditions of
|
||
society was not easy. A friend, who had read a great deal of what are
|
||
called the Moral Sciences, constantly said: ‘Ah\! if you understood
|
||
Political Economy you would not say that’” \[quoted by [Joan
|
||
Robinson](Joan_Robinson "wikilink"), Collected Economic Papers, vol.4,
|
||
p. 129\] Joan Robinson added that “\[n\]owadays, of course, no one would
|
||
put it so crudely. Nowadays, the hidden persuaders are concealed behind
|
||
scientific objectivity, carefully avoiding value judgements; they are
|
||
persuading all the better so.” \[Op. Cit., p. 129\]
|
||
|
||
The way which economic theory systematically says what bosses and the
|
||
wealthy want to hear is just one of those strange co-incidences of life,
|
||
one which seems to befall economics with alarming regularity. How does
|
||
economics achieve this strange co-incidence, how does the “value free”
|
||
“science” end up being wedded to producing apologetics for the current
|
||
system? A key reason is the lack of concern about history, about how the
|
||
current distribution of income and wealth was created. Instead, the
|
||
current distribution of wealth and income is taken for granted. This
|
||
flows, in part, from the static nature of neoclassical economics. If
|
||
your economic analysis starts and ends with a snapshot of time, with a
|
||
given set of commodities, then how those commodities get into a specific
|
||
set of hands can be considered irrelevant — particularly when you modify
|
||
your theory to exclude the possibility of proving income redistribution
|
||
will increaseoverall utility (see section
|
||
[C.1.3](C.1.3_\(An_Anarchist_FAQ\) "wikilink")).
|
||
|
||
It also flows from the social role of economics as defender of
|
||
capitalism. By taking the current distribution of income and wealth as
|
||
given, then many awkward questions can be automatically excluded from
|
||
the “science.” This can be seen from the rise of neoclassical economics
|
||
in the 1870s and 1880s. The break between classical political economy
|
||
and economics was marked by a change in the kind of questions being
|
||
asked. In the former, the central focus was on distribution, growth,
|
||
production and the relations between social classes. The exact
|
||
determination of individual prices was of little concern, particularly
|
||
in the short run. For the new economics, the focus became developing a
|
||
rigorous theory of price determination. This meant abstracting from
|
||
production and looking at the amount of goods available at any given
|
||
moment of time. Thus economics avoided questions about class relations
|
||
by asking questions about individual utility, so narrowing the field of
|
||
analysis by asking politically harmless questions based on unrealistic
|
||
models (for all its talk of rigour, the new economics did not provide an
|
||
answer to how real prices were determined any more than classical
|
||
economics had simply because its abstract models had no relation to
|
||
reality).
|
||
|
||
It did, however, provide a naturalistic justification for capitalist
|
||
social relations by arguing that profit,
|
||
[interest](Interest_\(Finance\) "wikilink") and [rent](rent "wikilink")
|
||
are the result of individual decisions rather than the product of a
|
||
specific social system. In other words, economics took the classes of
|
||
capitalism, internalised them within itself, gave them universal
|
||
application and, by taking for granted the existing distribution of
|
||
wealth, justified the class structure and differences in market power
|
||
this produces. It does not ask (or investigate) why some people own all
|
||
the [land](land "wikilink") and capital while the vast majority have to
|
||
sell their labour on the market to survive. As such, it internalises the
|
||
class structure of capitalism. Taking this class structure as a given,
|
||
economics simply asks the question how much does each “factor” (labour,
|
||
land, capital) contribute to the production of goods.
|
||
|
||
Alfred Marshall justified this perspective as follows: “In the long run
|
||
the earnings of each agent (of production) are, as a rule, sufficient
|
||
only to recompense the sum total of the efforts and sacrifices required
|
||
to produce them... with a partial exception in the case of land ...
|
||
especially much land in old countries, if we could trace its record back
|
||
to their earliest origins. But the attempt would raise controversial
|
||
questions in history and ethics as well as in economics; and the aims of
|
||
our present inquiry are prospective rather than retrospective.”
|
||
\[Principles of Economics, p.832\] Which is wonderfully handy for those
|
||
who benefited from the [theft](Enclosure "wikilink") of the [common
|
||
heritage of humanity](Commons "wikilink"). Particularly as Marshall
|
||
himself notes the dire consequences for those without access to the
|
||
means of life on the market: “When a workman is in fear of hunger, his
|
||
need of money is very great; and, if at starting he gets the worst of
|
||
the bargaining, it remains great ... That is all the more probably
|
||
because, while the advantage in bargaining is likely to be pretty well
|
||
distributed between the two sides of a market for commodities, it is
|
||
more often on the side of the buyers than on that of the sellers in a
|
||
market for labour.” \[Op. Cit., pp. 335–6\]
|
||
|
||
Given that market exchanges will benefit the stronger of the parties
|
||
involved, this means that inequalities become stronger and more secure
|
||
over time. Taking the current distribution of property as a given (and,
|
||
moreover, something that must not be changed) then the market does not
|
||
correct this sort of injustice. In fact, it perpetuates it and,
|
||
moreover, it has no way of compensating the victims as there is no
|
||
mechanism for ensuring reparations. So the impact of previous acts of
|
||
aggression has an impact on how a specific society developed and the
|
||
current state of the world. To dismiss “retrospective” analysis as it
|
||
raises “controversial questions" and “ethics” is not value-free or
|
||
objective science, it is pure ideology and skews any “prospective”
|
||
enquiry into apologetics. This can be seen when Marshall noted that
|
||
labour “is often sold under special disadvantages,arising from the
|
||
closely connected group of facts that labour power is ‘perishable,’ that
|
||
the sellers of it are commonly poor and have no reserve fund, and that
|
||
they cannot easily withhold it from the market.” Moreover, the
|
||
“disadvantage, wherever it exists, is likely to be cumulative in its
|
||
effects.” Yet, for some reason, he still maintains that “wages of every
|
||
class of labour tend to be equal to the net product due to the
|
||
additional labourer of this class.” \[Op. Cit., p. 567, p. 569 and p.
|
||
518\]
|
||
|
||
Why should it, given the noted fact that workers are at a disadvantage
|
||
in the market place? Hence Malatesta: “Landlords, capitalists have
|
||
robbed the people, with violence and dishonesty, of the land and all the
|
||
means of production, and in consequence of this initial theft can each
|
||
day take away from workers the product of their labour.”[\[Errico
|
||
Malatesta]([Errico_Malatesta "wikilink"): His Life and Ideas, p. 168\]
|
||
As such, how could it possibly be considered “scientific” or
|
||
“value-free” to ignore history? It is hardly “retrospective” to
|
||
analyse the roots of the current disadvantage working class people have
|
||
in the current and "prospective" labour market, particularly given that
|
||
Marshall himself notes their results. This is a striking example of what
|
||
Kropotkin deplored in economics, namely that in the rare situations when
|
||
social conditions were “mentioned, they were forgotten immediately, to
|
||
bespoken of no more.” Thus reality is mentioned, but any impact this may
|
||
have on the distribution of income is forgotten for otherwise you would
|
||
have to conclude, with the anarchists, that the “appropriation of the
|
||
produce of human labour by the owners of capital \[and land\] exists
|
||
only because millions of men \[and women\] have literally nothing to
|
||
live upon, unless they sell their labour force and their intelligence at
|
||
a price that will make the net profit of the capitalist and ‘surplus
|
||
value’ possible.”\[Evolution and Environment, p. 92 and p. 106\]
|
||
|
||
This is important, for respecting property rights is easy to talk about
|
||
but it only faintly holds some water if the existing property ownership
|
||
distribution is legitimate. If it is illegitimate, if the current
|
||
property titles were the result of theft, corruption, colonial conquest,
|
||
state intervention,and other forms of coercion then things are obviously
|
||
different. That is why economics rarely, if ever, discusses this. This
|
||
does not, of course, stop economists arguing against current
|
||
interventions in the market (particularly those associated with the
|
||
welfare state). In effect, they are arguing that it is okay to reap the
|
||
benefits of past initiations of force but it is wrong to try and rectify
|
||
them. It is as if someone walks into a room of people, robs them at gun
|
||
point and then asks that they should respect each others property rights
|
||
from now on and only engage in voluntary exchanges with what they had
|
||
left. Any attempt to establish a moral case for the “free market” in
|
||
such circumstances would be unlikely to succeed.
|
||
|
||
This is free market capitalist economics in a nutshell: never mind past
|
||
injustices, let us all do the best we can given the current allocations
|
||
of resources. Many economists go one better. Not content in ignoring
|
||
history, they create little fictional stories in order to justify their
|
||
theories or the current distribution of wealth and income. Usually, they
|
||
start from isolated individual or a community of approximately equal
|
||
individuals (ac ommunity usually without any communal institutions). For
|
||
example, the “waiting” theories of profit and interest (see section
|
||
[C.2.7](C.2.7_\(An_Anarchist_FAQ\) "wikilink")) requires such a fiction
|
||
to be remotely convincing. It needs to assume a community marked by
|
||
basic equality of wealth and income yet divided into two groups of
|
||
people, one of which was industrious and farsighted who abstained from
|
||
directly consuming the products created by their own labour while the
|
||
other was lazy and consumed their income without thought of the future.
|
||
Over time, the descendants of the diligent came to own the means of life
|
||
while the descendants of the lazy and the prodigal have, to quote Marx,
|
||
“nothing to sell but themselves.” In that way, modern day profits and
|
||
interest can be justified by appealing to such “insipid childishness.”
|
||
[Capital]([Das_Kapital "wikilink"), vol. 1, p. 873\]
|
||
|
||
The real history of the rise of capitalism is, as we discuss in section
|
||
[F.8](F.8_\(An_Anarchist_FAQ\) "wikilink"), grim. Of course, it may be
|
||
argued that this is just a model and an abstraction and, consequently,
|
||
valid to illustrate a point. Anarchists disagree. Yes, there is often
|
||
the need for abstraction in studying an economy or any other complex
|
||
system, but this is not an abstraction, it is propaganda and a
|
||
historical invention used not to illustrate an abstract point but rather
|
||
a specific system of power and class. That these little parables and
|
||
stories have all the necessary assumptions and abstractions required to
|
||
reach the desired conclusions is just one of those co-incidences which
|
||
seem to regularly befall economics.The strange thing about these
|
||
fictional stories is that they are given much more credence than real
|
||
history within economics. Almost always, fictional “history” will always
|
||
top actual history in economics.
|
||
|
||
If the actual history of capitalism is mentioned, then the defenders of
|
||
capitalism will simply say that we should not penalise current holders
|
||
of capital for actions in the dim and distant past (that current and
|
||
future generations of workers are penalised goes unmentioned).
|
||
However,the fictional “history” of capitalism suffers from no such
|
||
dismissal, for invented actions in the dim and distant past justify the
|
||
current owners holdings of wealth and the income that generates. In
|
||
other words, heads I win, tails you loose. Needless to say, this
|
||
(selective) myopia is not restricted to just history. It is applied to
|
||
current situations as well. Thus we find economists defending current
|
||
economic systems as “free market” regimes in spite of obvious forms of
|
||
state intervention. As Chomsky notes: “when people talk about ...
|
||
free-market ‘trade forces’ inevitably kicking all these people out of
|
||
work and driving the whole world towards a kind of a Third World-type
|
||
polarisation of wealth ... that’s true if you take a narrow enough
|
||
perspective on it. But if you look into the factors that made things the
|
||
way they are, it doesn’t even come close to being true, it’s not
|
||
remotely in touch with reality. But when you’re studying economics in
|
||
the ideological institutions, that’s all irrelevant and you’re not
|
||
supposed to ask questions like these.” [Understanding
|
||
Power]([Understanding_Power_\(Book\) "wikilink"), p. 260\]
|
||
|
||
To ignore all that and simply take the current distribution of wealth
|
||
and income as given and then argue that the “free market” produces the
|
||
best allocation of resources is staggering. Particularly as the claim of
|
||
“efficient allocation” does not address the obvious question:
|
||
“efficient” for whose benefit? For the idealisation of freedom in
|
||
and through the market ignores the fact that this freedom is very
|
||
limited in scope to great numbers of people as well as the consequences
|
||
to the individuals concerned by the distribution of purchasing power
|
||
amongst them that the market throws up (rooted, of course in the
|
||
original endowments). Which, of course, explains why, even if these
|
||
parables of economics were true, anarchists would still oppose
|
||
capitalism. We extend [Thomas Jefferson’s](Thomas_Jefferson "wikilink")
|
||
comment that the “earth belongs always to the living generation” to
|
||
economic institutions as well as political — the past should not
|
||
dominate the present and the future (Jefferson :“Can one generation bind
|
||
another and all others in succession forever? I think not.The Creator
|
||
has made the earth for the living, not for the dead. Rights and powers
|
||
can only belong to persons, not to things, not to mere matter un endowed
|
||
with will”).
|
||
|
||
For, as Malatesta argued, people should “not have the right ... to
|
||
subject people to their rule and even less of bequeathing to the
|
||
countless successions of their descendants the right to dominate and
|
||
exploit future generations.”\[At the Cafe, p. 48\] Then there is the
|
||
strange co-incidence that “value free” economics generally ends up
|
||
blaming all the problems of capitalism on workers. Unemployment?
|
||
Recession? Low growth? Wages are too high\! Proudhon summed up
|
||
capitalist economic theory well when he stated that "Political economy —
|
||
that is, proprietary despotism — can never be in the wrong: it must be
|
||
the proletariat.” [System of Economical
|
||
Contradictions]([System_of_Economical_Contradictions_\(Book\) "wikilink"),
|
||
p. 187\] And little has changed since 1846 (or 1776\!) when it comes to
|
||
economics “explaining” capitalism’s problems (such as the business cycle
|
||
or unemployment).
|
||
|
||
As such, it is hard to consider economics as “value free” when
|
||
economists regularly attack unions while being silent or supportive of
|
||
big business. According to neo-classical economic theory, both are meant
|
||
to be equally bad for the economy but you would be hard pressed to find
|
||
many economists who would urge the breaking up of corporations into a
|
||
multitude of small firms as their theory demands, the number who will
|
||
thunder against “monopolistic” labour is substantially higher
|
||
(ironically, as we note in section
|
||
[C.1.4](C.1.4_\(An_Anarchist_FAQ\) "wikilink"), their own theory shows
|
||
that they must urge the break up of corporations or support unions for,
|
||
otherwise, unorganised labour is exploited). Apparently arguing that
|
||
high wages are always bad but high profits are always good is value
|
||
free.
|
||
|
||
So while big business is generally ignored (in favour of arguments that
|
||
the economy works “as if” it did not exist), unions are rarely given
|
||
such favours. Unlike, say, transnational corporations, unions are
|
||
considered monopolistic. Thus we see the strange situation of economists
|
||
(or economics influenced ideologies like right-wing “libertarians”)
|
||
enthusiastically defending companies that raise their prices in the wake
|
||
of, say, a natural disaster and making windfall profits while, at the
|
||
same time, attacking workers who decide to raise their wages by striking
|
||
for being selfish. It is, of course, unlikely that they would let
|
||
similar charges against bosses pass without comment. But what can you
|
||
expect from an ideology which presents unemployment as a good thing
|
||
(namely, increased leisure — see section
|
||
[C.1.5](C.1.5_\(An_Anarchist_FAQ\) "wikilink")) and being rich as,
|
||
essentially, a disutility (the pain of abstaining from present
|
||
consumption falls heaviest on those with wealth — see section
|
||
[C.2.7](C.2.7_\(An_Anarchist_FAQ\) "wikilink")). Ultimately, only
|
||
economists would argue, with a straight face, that the billionaire owner
|
||
of a transnational corporation is exploited when the workers in his
|
||
sweatshops successfully form a union (usually in the face of the
|
||
economic and political power wielded by their boss).
|
||
|
||
Yet that is what many economists argue: the transnational corporation is
|
||
not a monopoly but the union is and monopolies exploit others\! Of
|
||
course, they rarely state it as bluntly as that. Instead they suggest
|
||
that unions get higher wages for their members be forcing other workers
|
||
to take less pay (i.e. by exploiting them). So when bosses break unions
|
||
they are doing this not to defend their profits and power but really to
|
||
raise the standard of other, less fortunate, workers? Hardly.In reality,
|
||
of course, the reason why unions are so disliked by economics is that
|
||
bosses, in general, hate them. Under capitalism, labour is a cost and
|
||
higher wages means less profits (all things being equal). Hence the need
|
||
to demonise unions, for one of the less understood facts is that while
|
||
unions increase wages for members, they also increase wages for
|
||
non-union workers.
|
||
|
||
This should not be surprising as non-union companies have to raise wages
|
||
stop their workers unionising and to compete for the best workers who
|
||
will be drawn to the better pay and conditions of union shops (as we
|
||
discuss in section [C.9](C.9_\(An_Anarchist_FAQ\) "wikilink"), the
|
||
neoclassical model of the labour market is seriouslyflawed).Which brings
|
||
us to another key problem with the claim that economics is “value free,”
|
||
namelythe fact that it takes the current class system of capitalism and
|
||
its distribution of wealth as notonly a fact but as an ideal. This is
|
||
because economics is based on the need to be able to
|
||
differentiatebetween each factor of production in order to determine if
|
||
it is being used optimally. In otherwords, the given class structure of
|
||
capitalism is required to show that an economy uses theavailable
|
||
resources efficiently or not. It claims to be “value free” simply
|
||
because it embeds theeconomic relationships of capitalist society into
|
||
its assumptions about nature.
|
||
|
||
Yet it is impossible to define profit, rent and interest independently
|
||
of the class structure of anygiven society. Therefore, this“type of
|
||
distribution is the peculiarity of capitalism. Under feudalismthe
|
||
surplus was extracted as land rent. In an artisan economy each commodity
|
||
is produced by a menwith his own tools; the distinction between wages
|
||
and profits has no meaning there.”This means that“the very essence of
|
||
the theory is bound up with a particular institution — wage labour. The
|
||
centraldoctrine is that ‘wages tend to equal marginal product of
|
||
labour.’ Obviously this has no meaning fora peasant household where
|
||
all share the work and the income of their holding according to the
|
||
rulesof family life; nor does it apply in a \[co-operative\] where, the
|
||
workers’ council has to decide whatpart of net proceeds to allot to
|
||
investment, what part to a welfare found and what part to distributeas
|
||
wage.”\[Joan Robinson,Collected Economic Papers, p. 26 and p. 130\]
|
||
|
||
This means that the “universal” principles of economics end up by making
|
||
any economy whichdoesnotshare the core social relations of capitalism
|
||
inherently “inefficient.” If, for example, work-ers own all three
|
||
“factors of production” (labour, land and capital) then the
|
||
“value-free” laws ofeconomics concludes that this will be inefficient.
|
||
As there is only “income”, it is impossible to saywhich part of it is
|
||
attributable to labour, land or machinery and, consequently, if these
|
||
factors arebeing efficiently used. This means that the “science” of
|
||
economics is bound up with the currentsystem and its specific class
|
||
structure and, therefore, as a“ruling class paradigm, the
|
||
competitivemodel”has the“substantial”merit that“it can be used to rule
|
||
off the agenda any proposals for25substantial reform or intervention
|
||
detrimental to large economic interests ... as the model allows (onits
|
||
assumptions) a formal demonstration that these would reduce
|
||
efficiency.”\[Edward S. Herman,“The Selling of Market Economics,”pp.
|
||
173–199,New Ways of Knowing, Marcus G. Raskin andHerbert J. Bernstein
|
||
(eds.), p. 178\]
|
||
|
||
Then there are the methodological assumptions based on individualism. By
|
||
concentrating onindividual choices, economics abstracts from the social
|
||
system within which such choices aremade and what influences them. Thus,
|
||
for example, the analysis of the causes of poverty is turnedtowards the
|
||
failings of individuals rather than the system as a whole (to be poor
|
||
becomes apersonal stigma). That the reality on the ground bears little
|
||
resemblance to the myth matters little— when people with two jobs still
|
||
fail to earn enough to feed their families, it seems ridiculousto call
|
||
them lazy or selfish. It suggests a failure in the system, not in the
|
||
poor themselves. Anindividualistic analysis is guaranteed to exclude, by
|
||
definition, the impact of class, inequality,social hierarchies and
|
||
economic/social power and any analysis of any inherent biases in a
|
||
giveneconomic system, its distribution of wealth and, consequently, its
|
||
distribution of income betweenclasses.This abstracting of individuals
|
||
from their social surroundings results in the generating eco-nomic
|
||
“laws” which are applicable for all individuals, in all societies,
|
||
for all times. This resultsin all concrete instances, no matter how
|
||
historically different, being treated as expressions ofthe same
|
||
universal concept. In this way the uniqueness of contemporary society,
|
||
namely its ba-sis in wage labour, is ignored (“The period through which
|
||
we are passing ... is distinguished by aspecial characteristic —
|
||
WAGES.”\[Proudhon,Op. Cit., p. 199\]).
|
||
|
||
Such a perspective cannot helpbeing ideological rather than scientific.
|
||
By trying to create a theory applicable for all time (andso, apparently,
|
||
value free) they just hide the fact their theory assumes and justifies
|
||
the inequal-ities of capitalism (for example, the assumption of given
|
||
needs and distribution of wealth andincome secretly introduces the
|
||
social relations of the current society back into the model, some-thing
|
||
which the model had supposedly abstracted from). By stressing
|
||
individualism, scarcity andcompetition, in reality economic analysis
|
||
reflects nothing more than the dominant ideologicalconceptions found in
|
||
capitalist society. Every few economic systems or societies in the
|
||
historyof humanity have actually reflected these aspects of capitalism
|
||
(indeed, a lot of state violence hasbeen used to create these conditions
|
||
by breaking up traditional forms of society, property rightsand customs
|
||
in favour of those desired by the current ruling elite).The very general
|
||
nature of the various theories of profit, interest and rent should send
|
||
alarmbells ringing. Their authors construct these theories based on the
|
||
deductive method and stresshow they are applicable ineverysocial and
|
||
economic system.
|
||
|
||
In other words, the theories arejust that, theories derived
|
||
independently of the facts of the society they are in. It seems
|
||
somewhatstrange, to say the least, to develop a theory of, say, interest
|
||
independently of the class systemwithin which it is charged but this is
|
||
precisely what these “scientists” do. It is understandablewhy. By
|
||
ignoring the current system and its classes and hierarchies, the
|
||
economic aspects ofthis system can be justified in terms of appeals to
|
||
universal human existence. This will raise lessobjections than saying,
|
||
for example, that interest exists because the rich will only part with
|
||
theirmoney if they get more in return and the poor will pay for this
|
||
because they have little choicedue to their socio-economic situation.
|
||
Far better to talk about “time preference” rather than thereality of
|
||
class society (see section C.2.6).Neoclassical economics, in effect,
|
||
took the “political” out of “political economy” by takingcapitalist
|
||
society for granted along with its class system, its hierarchies and its
|
||
inequalities.
|
||
|
||
This is reflected in the terminology used. These days even the term
|
||
capitalism has gone out of fashion,replaced with the approved
|
||
terms“market system,”the“free market”or“free enterprise.”Yet,as
|
||
Chomsky noted, terms such as“free enterprise”are used“to designate a
|
||
system of autocraticgovernance of the economy in which neither the
|
||
community nor the workforce has any role (a systemwe would call
|
||
‘fascist’ if translated to the political sphere).”\[Language and
|
||
Politics, p. 175\] As such,it seems hardly “value-free” to proclaim a
|
||
system free when, in reality, most people are distinctlynot free for
|
||
most of their waking hours and whose choices outside production are
|
||
influenced bythe inequality of wealth and power which that system of
|
||
production create.This shift in terminology reflects a political
|
||
necessity. It effectively removes the role of wealth(capital) from the
|
||
economy. Instead of the owners and manager of capital being in control
|
||
or,at the very least, having significant impact on social events, we
|
||
have the impersonal activityof“the markets”or“market forces.”That such a
|
||
change in terminology is the interest of thosewhose money accords them
|
||
power and influence goes without saying.
|
||
|
||
By focusing on the market,economics helps hide the real sources of power
|
||
in an economy and attention is drawn awayfrom such a key questions of
|
||
how money (wealth) produces power and how it skews the “freemarket” in
|
||
its favour. All in all, as dissident economist John Kenneth Galbraith
|
||
once put it,“\[w\]hateconomists believe and teach is rarely hostile to
|
||
the institutions that reflect the dominant economicpower. Not to notice
|
||
this takes effort, although many succeed.”\[The Essential Galbraith, p.
|
||
180\]This becomes obvious when we look at how the advice economics gives
|
||
to working classpeople. In theory, economics is based on individualism
|
||
and competition yet when it comes towhat workers should do, the “laws”
|
||
of economics suddenly switch. The economist will now denythat
|
||
competition is a good idea and instead urge that the workers co-operate
|
||
(i.e. obey) their bossrather than compete (i.e. struggle over the
|
||
division of output and authority in the workplace).
|
||
|
||
They will argue that there is“harmony of interests”between worker and
|
||
boss, that it is in theself-interest of workersnotto be selfish but
|
||
rather to do whatever the boss asks to furtherthebossesinterests (i.e.
|
||
profits).That this perspective implicitly recognises
|
||
thedependentposition of workers, goes withoutsaying. So while the sale
|
||
of labour is portrayed as a market exchange between equals, it is infact
|
||
an authority relation between servant and master. The conclusions of
|
||
economics is simplyimplicitly acknowledging that authoritarian
|
||
relationship by identifying with the authority figurein the relationship
|
||
and urging obedience to them. It simply suggests workers make the best
|
||
of itby refusing to be independent individuals who need freedom to
|
||
flourish (at least during workinghours, outside they can express their
|
||
individuality by shopping).This should come as no surprise, for, as
|
||
Chomsky notes, economics is rooted in the notion that“you only harm the
|
||
poor by making them believe that they have rights other than what they
|
||
can winon the market, like a basic right to live, because that kind of
|
||
right interferes with the market, andwith efficiency, and with growth
|
||
and so on — so ultimately people will just be worse off if you try
|
||
torecognise them.”\[Op. Cit., p. 251\]
|
||
|
||
Economics teaches that you must accept change without regardto whether
|
||
it is appropriate it not. It teaches that you must not struggle, you
|
||
must not fight. Youmust simply accept whatever change happens. Worse, it
|
||
teaches that resisting and fighting backare utterly counter-productive.
|
||
In other words, it teaches a servile mentality to those subject
|
||
toauthority. For business, economics is ideal for getting their
|
||
employees to change their attitudesrather than collectively change how
|
||
their bosses treat them, structure their jobs or how they arepaid — or,
|
||
of course, change the system.27Of course, the economist who says that
|
||
they are conducting “value free” analysis are indif-ferent to the kinds
|
||
of relationships within society is being less than honest. Capitalist
|
||
economictheory is rooted in very specific assumptions and concepts such
|
||
as “economic man” and “per-fect competition.” It claims to be
|
||
“value-free” yet its preferred terminology is riddled with
|
||
valueconnotations. For example, the behaviour of “economic man” (i.e.,
|
||
people who are self-interestedutility maximisation machines) is
|
||
described as“rational.”
|
||
|
||
By implication, then, the behaviour ofreal people is“irrational”whenever
|
||
they depart from this severely truncated account of humannature and
|
||
society. Our lives consist of much more than buying and selling. We have
|
||
goals andconcerns which cannot be bought or sold in markets. In other
|
||
words, humanity and liberty tran-scend the limits of property and, as a
|
||
result, economics. This, unsurprisingly, affects those whostudy the
|
||
“science” as well:“Studying economics also seems to make you a nastier
|
||
person. Psychological studieshave shown that economics graduate students
|
||
are more likely to ‘free ride’ — shirk con-tributions to an experimental
|
||
‘public goods’ account in the pursuit of higher privatereturns — than
|
||
the general public. Economists also are less generous that other
|
||
aca-demics in charitable giving. Undergraduate economics majors are more
|
||
likely to defectin the classic prisoner’s dilemma game that are other
|
||
majors.
|
||
|
||
And on other tests, stu-dents grow less honest — expressing less of a
|
||
tendency, for example, to return foundmoney — after studying economics,
|
||
but not studying a control subject like astronomy.“This is no surprise,
|
||
really. Mainstream economics is built entirely on a notion of
|
||
self-interested individuals, rational self-maximisers who can order
|
||
their wants and spendaccordingly. There’s little room for sentiment,
|
||
uncertainty, selflessness, and social insti-tutions. Whether this is an
|
||
accurate picture of the average human is open to question,but there’s no
|
||
question that capitalism as a system and economics as a discipline
|
||
bothreward people who conform to the model.”\[Doug Henwood,Wall Street,
|
||
p, 143\]So is economics “value free”? Far from it. Given its social
|
||
role, it would be surprising that itwere. That it tends to produce
|
||
policy recommendations that benefit the capitalist class is notan
|
||
accident. It is rooted in the fibre of the “science” as it reflects the
|
||
assumptions of capitalistsociety and its class structure. Not only does
|
||
it take the power and class structures of capital-ism for granted, it
|
||
also makes them the ideal for any and every economy.
|
||
|
||
Given this, it shouldcome as no surprise that economists will tend to
|
||
support policies which will make the real worldconform more closely to
|
||
the standard (usually neoclassical) economic model. Thus the modelsof
|
||
economics become more than a set of abstract assumptions, used simply as
|
||
a tool in theoreti-cal analysis of the casual relations of facts. Rather
|
||
they become political goals, an ideal towardswhich reality should be
|
||
forced to travel.This means that economics has a dual character. On the
|
||
one hand, it attempts to prove thatcertain things (for example, that
|
||
free market capitalism produces an optimum allocation of re-sources or
|
||
that, given free competition, price formation will ensure that each
|
||
person’s incomecorresponds to their productive contribution). On the
|
||
other, economists stress that economic“science” has nothing to do with
|
||
the question of the justice of existing institutions, class struc-tures
|
||
or the current economic system. And some people seem surprised that this
|
||
results in policyrecommendations which consistently and systematically
|
||
favour the ruling class |