283 lines
18 KiB
Markdown
283 lines
18 KiB
Markdown
**C.1.2 Is economics a science?** is the third chapter of [Section
|
||
C](Section_C:_What_are_the_myths_of_capitalist_economics?_\(An_Anarchist_FAQ\) "wikilink")
|
||
of [An Anarchist FAQ](An_Anarchist_FAQ "wikilink").
|
||
|
||
## Transcript
|
||
|
||
In a word, no. If by “[scientific](Science "wikilink")” it is meant in
|
||
the usual sense of being based on empirical observation and on
|
||
developing an analysis that was consistent with and made sense of the
|
||
data, then most forms of economics are not a science. Rather than base
|
||
itself on a study of reality and the generalisation of theory based on
|
||
the data gathered, economics has almost always been based on generating
|
||
theories rooted on whatever assumptions were required to make the theory
|
||
work. Empirical confirmation, if it happens at all, is usually done
|
||
decades later and if the facts contradict the economics, so much the
|
||
worse for the facts.
|
||
|
||
A classic example of this is the neo-classical theory of production. As
|
||
noted previously, neoclassical economics is focused on individual
|
||
evaluations of existing products and, unsurprisingly, economics is
|
||
indelibly marked by “the dominance of a theoretical vision that treats
|
||
the inner workings of the production process as a ‘black box.’” This
|
||
means that the “neoclassical theory of the ‘capitalist’ economy makes no
|
||
qualitative distinction between the [corporate](Corporation "wikilink")
|
||
enterprise that employs tens of thousands of people and the small family
|
||
undertaking that does no employ any [wage
|
||
labour](Wage_Labour "wikilink") at all. As far as theory is concerned,
|
||
it is technology and market forces, not structures of social power, that
|
||
govern the activities of corporate capitalists and petty proprietors
|
||
alike.” \[William Lazonick, Competitive Advantage on the Shop Floor, p.
|
||
34 and pp. 33–4\]
|
||
|
||
Production in this schema just happens — inputs go in, outputs go out —
|
||
and what happens inside is considered irrelevant, a technical issue
|
||
independent of the social relationships those who do the actual
|
||
production form between themselves — and the conflicts that ensure. The
|
||
theory does have a few key assumptions associated with it, however.
|
||
First, there are diminishing returns. This plays a central role. In
|
||
mainstream diminishing returns are required to produce a downward
|
||
sloping demand curve for a given factor. Second, there is a rising
|
||
supply curve based on rising marginal costs produced by diminishing
|
||
returns. The average variable cost curve for a firm is assumed to be
|
||
U-shaped, the result of first increasing and then diminishing returns.
|
||
These are logically necessary for the neo-classical theory to work.
|
||
|
||
Non-economists would, of course, think that these assumptions are
|
||
generalisations based on empirical evidence. However, they are not. Take
|
||
the U-shaped average cost curve. This was simply invented by [A. C.
|
||
Pigou](Arthur_Cecil_Pigou "wikilink"), “a loyal disciple of \[leading
|
||
neo-classical Alfred\] Marshall and quite innocent of any knowledge of
|
||
industry. He therefore constructed a U-shaped average cost curve for a
|
||
firm, showing [economies of scale](Economy_of_Scale "wikilink") up to a
|
||
certain size and rising costs beyond it.” [\[Joan
|
||
Robinson]([Joan_Robinson "wikilink"), Collected Economic Papers, vol. 5,
|
||
p. 11\] The invention was driven by need of the theory, not the facts.
|
||
With increasing returns to scale, then large firms would have cost
|
||
advantages against small ones and would drive them out of business in
|
||
competition.
|
||
|
||
This would destroy the concept of perfect competition. However, the
|
||
invention of the average cost curve allowed the theory to work as
|
||
“proved” that a competitive market could not become dominated by a few
|
||
large firms, as feared. The model, in other words, was adjusted to
|
||
ensure that it produced the desired result rather than reflect reality.
|
||
The theory was required to prove that markets remained competitive and
|
||
the existence of diminishing marginal returns to scale of production did
|
||
tend by itself to limit the size of individual firms. That markets did
|
||
become dominated by a few large firms was neither here nor there. It did
|
||
not happen in theory and, consequently, that was the important thing and
|
||
so “when the great concentrations of power in the multinational
|
||
corporations are bringing the age of national employment policy to an
|
||
end, the text books are still illustrated by U-shaped curves showing the
|
||
limitation on the size of firms in a perfectly competitive market.”
|
||
\[Joan Robinson, Contributions to Modern Economics, p. 5\]
|
||
|
||
To be good, a theory must have two attributes: They accurately describe
|
||
the phenomena in question and they make accurate predictions. Neither
|
||
holds for Pigou’s invention: reality keeps getting in the way. Not only
|
||
did the rise of a few large firms dominating markets indirectly show
|
||
that the theory was nonsense, when empirical testing was finally done
|
||
decades after the theory was proposed it showed that in most cases the
|
||
opposite is the case: that there were constant or even falling costs in
|
||
production. Just as the theories of marginality and diminishing marginal
|
||
returns taking over economics, the real world was showing how wrong it
|
||
was with the rise of [corporations](Corporation "wikilink") across the
|
||
world. So the reason why the market become dominated by a few firms
|
||
should be obvious enough: actual corporate price is utterly different
|
||
from the economic theory.
|
||
|
||
This was discovered when researchers did what the original theorists did
|
||
not think was relevant: they actually asked firms what they did and the
|
||
researchers consistently found that, for the vast majority of
|
||
manufacturing firms their average costs of production declined as output
|
||
rose, their marginal costs were always well below their average costs,
|
||
and substantially smaller than ‘marginal revenue’, and the concept of a
|
||
‘demand curve’ (and therefore its derivative ‘marginal revenue’) was
|
||
simply irrelevant. Unsurprisingly, real firms set their
|
||
[prices](Price "wikilink") prior to sales, based on a mark-up on costs
|
||
at a target rate of output.
|
||
|
||
In other words, they did not passively react to the market. These prices
|
||
are an essential feature of capitalism as prices are set to maintain the
|
||
long-term viability of the firm. This, and the underlying reality that
|
||
per-unit costs fell as output levels rose, resulted in far more stable
|
||
prices than were predicted by traditional economic theory. One
|
||
researcher concluded that administered prices “differ so sharply from
|
||
the behaviour to be expected from” the theory “as to challenge the basic
|
||
conclusions” of it. He warned that until such time as “economic theory
|
||
can explain and take into account the implications” of this empirical
|
||
data, “it provides a poor basis for public policy.” Needless to say,
|
||
this did not disturb neo-classical economists or stop them providing
|
||
public policy recommendations. \[Gardiner C. Means, “The
|
||
Administered-Price Thesis Reconfirmed”,The American Economic Review, pp.
|
||
292–306, Vol. 62, No. 3, p. 304\]
|
||
|
||
One study in 1952 showed firms a range of hypothetical cost curves, and
|
||
asked firms which ones most closely approximated their own costs. Over
|
||
90% of firms chose a graph with a declining average cost rather than one
|
||
showing the conventional economic theory of rising marginal costs. These
|
||
firms faced declining average cost, and their marginal revenues were
|
||
much greater than marginal cost at all levels of output. Unsurprisingly,
|
||
the study’s authors concluded if this sample was typical then it was
|
||
“obvious that short-run marginal price theory should be revised in the
|
||
light of reality.” We are still waiting. \[Eiteman and Guthrie, “The
|
||
Shape of the Average Cost Curve”, The American Economic Review, pp.
|
||
832–8, Vol. 42, No. 5, p. 838\]
|
||
|
||
A more recent study of the empirical data came to the same conclusions,
|
||
arguing that it is “overwhelming bad news ... for economic theory.”
|
||
While economists treat rising marginal cost as the rule, 89% of firms in
|
||
the study reported marginal costs which were either constant or declined
|
||
with output. As for price elasticity, it is not a vital operational
|
||
concept for corporations. In other words, the “firms that sell 40
|
||
percent of GDP believe their demand is totally insensitive to price”
|
||
while “only about one-sixth of GDP is sold under conditions of elastic
|
||
demand.” \[A.S. Blinder, E. Cabetti, D. Lebow and J. Rudd, Asking About
|
||
Prices, p. 102 and p. 101\]
|
||
|
||
Thus empirical research has concluded that actual price setting has
|
||
nothing to do with clearing the market by equating market supply to
|
||
market demand (i.e. what economic theory sees as the role of prices).
|
||
Rather, prices are set to enable the firm to continue as a going concern
|
||
and equating supply and demand in any arbitrary period of time is
|
||
irrelevant to a firm which hopes to exist for the indefinite future. As
|
||
Lee put it, basing himself on extensive use of empirical research,
|
||
“market prices are not market-clearing or profit-maximising prices,
|
||
but rather are enterprise-, and hence transaction-reproducing prices.”
|
||
Rather than a non-existent equilibrium or profit maximisation at a given
|
||
moment determining prices, the market price is \<em\>“set and the market
|
||
managed for the purpose of ensuring continual transactions for those
|
||
enterprises in the market, that is for the benefit of the business
|
||
leaders and their enterprises.” A significant proportion of goods have
|
||
prices based on mark-up, normal cost and target rate of return pricing
|
||
procedures and are relatively stable over time. Thus “the existence of
|
||
stable, administered market prices implies that the markets in which
|
||
they exist are not organised like auction markets or like the early
|
||
retail markets and oriental bazaars” as imagined in mainstream economic
|
||
ideology. \[Frederic S. Lee, Post Keynesian Price Theory, p. 228 and p.
|
||
212\]
|
||
|
||
Unsurprisingly, most of these researchers were highly critical the
|
||
conventional economic theory of markets and price setting. One viewed
|
||
the economists’ concepts of perfect competition and monopoly as virtual
|
||
nonsense and \<em\>“the product of the itching imaginations of
|
||
uninformed and inexperienced armchair theorisers.”\</em\> \[Tucker,
|
||
quoted by Lee, \<strong\>Op. Cit.\</strong\>, p. 73f\] Which
|
||
\<strong\>was\</strong\> exactly how it was produced. No other science
|
||
would think it appropriate to develop theory utterly independently of
|
||
phenomenon under analysis. No other science would wait decades before
|
||
testing a theory against reality. No other science would then simply
|
||
ignore the facts which utterly contradicted the theory and continue to
|
||
teach that theory as if it were a valid generalisation of the facts.
|
||
But, then, economics is not a science. This strange perspective makes
|
||
sense once it is realised how key the notion of diminishing costs is to
|
||
economics. In fact, if the assumption of increasing marginal costs is
|
||
abandoned then so is perfect competition and \<em\>“the basis of which
|
||
economic laws can be constructed ... is shorn away,”\</em\> causing the
|
||
\<em\>“wreckage of the greater part of general equilibrium
|
||
theory.”\</em\> This will have \<em\>“a very destructive consequence
|
||
for economic theory,”\</em\> in the words of one leading neo-classical
|
||
economist. \[John Hicks, \<strong\>Value and Capital\</strong\>, pp.
|
||
83–4\] As Steve Keen notes, this is extremely significant: <quote>
|
||
\<em\> “Strange as it may seem ... this is a very big deal. If marginal
|
||
returns are constant rather than falling, then the neo-classical
|
||
explanation of everything collapses. Not only can economic theory no
|
||
longer explain how much a firm produces, it can explain nothing
|
||
else.\</em\> \<em\>“Take, for example, the economic theory of employment
|
||
and wage determination ... The theory asserts that the real wage is
|
||
equivalent to the marginal product of labour ... An employer will employ
|
||
an additional worker if the amount the worker adds to output — the
|
||
worker’s marginal product — exceeds the real wage ... \[This\] explains
|
||
the economic predilection for blaming everything on wages being too high
|
||
— neo-classical economics can be summed up, as \[John Kenneth\]
|
||
Galbraith once remarked, in the twin propositions that the poor don’t
|
||
work hard enough because they’re paid too much, and the rich don’t work
|
||
hard enough because they’re not paid enough ...\</em\> \<em\>“If in fact
|
||
the output to employment relationship is relatively constant, then the
|
||
neo-classical explanation for employment and output determination
|
||
collapses. With a flat production function, the marginal product of
|
||
labour will be constant, and it will \<strong\>never\</strong\>
|
||
intersect the real wage. The output of the form then can’t be explained
|
||
by the cost of employing labour... \[This means that\] neo-classical
|
||
economics simply cannot explain anything: neither the level of
|
||
employment, nor output, nor, ultimately, what determines the real wage
|
||
...the entire edifice of economics collapses.”\</em\>
|
||
\[\<strong\>Debunking Economics\</strong\>, pp. 76–7\] \</quote\> It
|
||
should be noted that the empirical research simply confirmed an earlier
|
||
critique of neo-classical economics presented by Piero Sraffa in 1926.
|
||
He argued that while the neo-classical model of production works in
|
||
theory only if we accept its assumptions. If those assumptions do not
|
||
apply in practice, then it is irrelevant. He therefore \<em\>“focussed
|
||
upon the economic assumptions that there were ‘factors of production’
|
||
which were fixed in the short run, and that supply and demand were
|
||
independent of each other. He argued that these two assumptions could be
|
||
fulfilled simultaneously. In circumstances where it was valid to say
|
||
some factor of production was fixed in the short term, supply and demand
|
||
could not independent, so that every point on the supply curve would be
|
||
associated with a different demand curve. On the other hand, in
|
||
circumstances where supply and demand could justifiably be treated as
|
||
independent, then it would be impossible for any factor of production to
|
||
be fixed. Hence the marginal costs of production would be
|
||
constant.”\</em\> He stressed firms would have to be irrational to act
|
||
otherwise, foregoing the chance to make profits simply to allow
|
||
economists to build their models of how they should act. \[Keen,
|
||
\<strong\>Op. Cit.\</strong\>, pp. 66–72\] Another key problem in
|
||
economics is that of time. This has been known, and admitted, by
|
||
economists for some time. Marshall, for example, stated that \<em\>“the
|
||
element of \<strong\>time\</strong\>”\</em\> was \<em\>“the source of
|
||
many of the greatest difficulties of economics.”\</em\>
|
||
\[\<strong\>Principles of Economics\</strong\>, p. 109\] The founder of
|
||
general equilibrium theory, Walras, recognised that the passage of time
|
||
wrecked his whole model and stated that we \<em\>“shall resolve the ...
|
||
difficulty purely and simply by ignoring the time element at this
|
||
point.”\</em\> This was due, in part, because production
|
||
\<em\>“requires a certain lapse of time.”\</em\> \[\<strong\>Elements
|
||
of Pure Economics\</strong\>, p. 242\] This was generalised by Gerard
|
||
Debreu (in his Nobel Prize for economics winning \<strong\>Theory of
|
||
Value\</strong\> ) who postulated that everyone makes their sales and
|
||
purchases for all time in one instant. Thus the cutting edge of
|
||
neo-classical economics, general equilibrium ignores both time
|
||
\<strong\>and\</strong\> production. It is based on making time stop,
|
||
looking at finished goods, getting individuals to bid for them and, once
|
||
all goods are at equilibrium, allowing the transactions to take place.
|
||
For Walras, this was for a certain moment of time and was repeated, for
|
||
his followers it happened once for all eternity. This is obviously not
|
||
the way markets work in the real world and, consequently, the dominant
|
||
branch of economics is hardly scientific. Sadly, the notion of
|
||
individuals having full knowledge of both now and the future crops up
|
||
with alarming regularly in the “science” of economics. Even if we ignore
|
||
such minor issues as empirical evidence and time, economics has problems
|
||
even with its favoured tool, mathematics. As Steve Keen has indicated,
|
||
economists have \<em\>“obscured reality using mathematics because they
|
||
have practised mathematics badly, and because they have not realised the
|
||
limits of mathematics.”\</em\> indeed, there are \<em\>“numerous
|
||
theorems in economics that reply upon mathematically fallacious
|
||
propositions.”\</em\> \[\<strong\>Op. Cit.\</strong\>, p. 258 and p.
|
||
259\] For a theory born from the desire to apply calculus to economics,
|
||
this is deeply ironic. As an example, Keen points to the theory of
|
||
perfect competition which assumes that while the demand curve for the
|
||
market as a whole is downward sloping, an individual firm in perfect
|
||
competition is so small that it cannot affect the market price and,
|
||
consequently, faces a horizontal demand curve. Which is utterly
|
||
impossible. In other words, economics breaks the laws of mathematics.
|
||
These are just two examples, there are many, many more. However, these
|
||
two are pretty fundamental to the whole edifice of modern economic
|
||
theory. Much, if not most, of mainstream economics is based upon
|
||
theories which have little or no relation to reality. Kropotkin’s
|
||
dismissal of \<em\>“the metaphysical definitions of the academical
|
||
economists”\</em\> is as applicable today. \[\<strong\>Evolution and
|
||
Environment\</strong\>, p. 92\] Little wonder dissident economist
|
||
Nicholas Kaldor argued that: <quote> \<em\> “The Walrasian \[i.e.
|
||
general\] equilibrium theory is a highly developed intellectual system,
|
||
much refined and elaborated by mathematical economists since World War
|
||
II — an intellectual experiment ... But it does not constitute a
|
||
scientific hypothesis, like Einstein’s theory of relativity or Newton’s
|
||
law of gravitation, in that its basic assumptions are axiomatic and not
|
||
empirical, and no specific methods have been put forward by which the
|
||
validity or relevance of its results could be tested. The assumptions
|
||
make assertions about reality in their implications, but these are not
|
||
founded on direct observation, and, in the opinion of practitioners of
|
||
the theory at any rate, they cannot be contradicted by observation or
|
||
experiment.”\</em\> \[\<strong\>The Essential Kaldor\</strong\>, p.
|
||
416\] \</quote\> |